My position is that what we are informs how we ought to be treated.CaptainFritz28 wrote: ↑Fri May 23, 2025 2:18 amWhat I find interesting about your stance is that, if taken with consideration of your belief in biological evolution (presumably from non-life to where we are now), this implies that 200 years ago, you would've argued that abortion is not a right, as it had a high risk of incurring suffering upon the mother (I could mention the suffering that it causes the child, but I'll leave that out because I only mean to use abortion as an example), whereas now you argue that it is because it doesn't cause such suffering. What I wonder is how this is so much a product of biology as it is of technology (we are, even per Darwinian evolution, basically no different than we were 200 years ago, and we're no smarter, we just have more tech, which has its origins on what we had).Esquire Bertissimmo wrote: ↑Thu May 22, 2025 5:37 pmAnd I would argue it is tangible. Human bodies (and maybe some other biology) insatiate suffering. An enslaved person's yearning to be free is a fact about the universe. It's not a *necessary* fact about the universe—a clever eugenicist in the year 2200 might be able to gene edit a non-suffering slave human. But it's true today.
[...]
It's "subjective" in the sense that it's reliant upon our biology. The rights that flow from what we are as creatures probably largely don't apply to amoeba and trees, but might apply in many relevant cases to, say, chimpanzees.
Your position, then, appears to be that rights change as we do, not biologically but technologically, in that biologically, the goal is the same, and technologically, we may be able to do certain things without hindering that goal that we couldn't do before.
Reproductive autonomy is one fundamental part of that. So is the right to life. Abortion has always involved a conflict of rights—between the fetus’s right to life and the mother’s right to reproductive autonomy (and, in some cases, her right to life as well). How we think about that conflict should take into account a range of circumstances: the stage of gestation, health risks to the mother, whether the pregnancy resulted from incest, and so on. It also includes technological factors (e.g., the safety of the procedure, fetal viability) and social ones (e.g., whether we hold fathers accountable, support early childhood, or provide alternatives like adoption). Your post thinks about technology only going in one way (reducing the moral weight of abortion by reducing risks to the mother), but it in fact goes both ways (by making fetus viable earlier and earlier within pregnancy).
The rights themselves—rooted in our biology and capacity for suffering—don’t shift quickly. But how those rights are applied or balanced depends on the surrounding reality, which includes technology, institutions, and culture.
That’s actually a hopeful thing if you believe in moral progress. We've developed societies and tools that are more rights-promoting than what came before, not because our biology changed, but because we’ve done better at recognizing and accommodating it.